From Zarathustra to Transhumanism: The Evolution of Human Enhancement

Nietzsche was one of the most influential philosophers of the 19th century. One of Nietzsche’s central ideas was the concept of the will to power. He argued that all living beings had an innate desire to exert their power and influence over their surroundings. This idea has interesting implications for our understanding of artificial intelligence. AI systems are designed to be powerful, to process vast amounts of data and make decisions that would be impossible for humans to make on their own. In this sense, they embody the will to power that Nietzsche described.

Moreover, Nietzsche’s ideas about the death of God and the loss of traditional sources of meaning in modern society are particularly relevant in the context of AI. As we create more intelligent machines, we may find that they challenge our assumptions about what it means to be human. They may be able to perform tasks that were previously thought to require human intelligence, such as creating art, composing music, or writing poetry. This could lead to a crisis of identity and purpose for humans, as we struggle to find our place in a world where machines are increasingly able to replace us.

However, it is worth noting that Nietzsche’s ideas were often misunderstood and misused in the past. His concepts of the Ubermensch and the will to power were twisted by the Nazis to justify their ideology of racial superiority and violence. It is important to approach Nietzsche’s ideas with caution and to recognize the dangers of using them to justify unethical behavior.

The concept of transhumanism, or the idea that humans can and should transcend their biological limitations through the use of technology, has become increasingly popular in recent years. But this is not a new idea – in fact, it can be seen as an outgrowth of a very basic human sentiment that has been present throughout history: the will to power, as espoused by the Nietzsche.

Nietzsche’s concept of the ubermensch, or “superman,” was a vision of a new kind of human being who would transcend the limitations of traditional morality and create their own values and meanings in life. This vision of the ubermensch can be seen as a precursor to the transhumanist movement, which seeks to use technology to enhance human capabilities and create a new kind of human being.

At its core, the will to power is the drive to exert one’s power and influence over one’s surroundings, to achieve greatness and self-mastery. This drive is evident in the transhumanist movement, which seeks to use technology to transcend the limitations of our biological bodies and minds. Through the use of technologies like genetic engineering, cybernetics, and artificial intelligence, transhumanists believe that we can create a new kind of human being that is more powerful, intelligent, and capable than ever before.

But while the transhumanist movement may seem like a radical departure from traditional humanism, it is in fact an outgrowth of a very basic human sentiment. Throughout history, humans have sought to transcend their limitations and achieve greatness through various means – whether through religion, art, or science. The transhumanist movement can be seen as the latest iteration of this drive to transcend ourselves and achieve something greater.

Of course, Nietzsche could not have predicted the breakthroughs in technology that have arrived since his death. But even during his era, there were the initial currents of technological advancements that would go on to shape our world today. Nietzsche was keenly aware of the transformative power of technology, and he saw it as a way to further the will to power.

The parallels between Nietzsche’s will to power and the transhumanist movement are clear. Both seek to transcend the limitations of traditional human existence and create a new kind of human being that is more powerful and capable than ever before. Both are driven by a basic human sentiment – the desire to achieve greatness and self-mastery. And both are deeply rooted in the transformative power of technology.

But as with any new technology, there are also risks and challenges associated with the transhumanist movement. The potential for unintended consequences, such as the creation of new forms of inequality or the loss of our humanity, must be carefully considered. And we must also ask ourselves whether the pursuit of greater power and capability is truly the path to a better future, or whether there are other values and goals that should take precedence.

As I noted the connection between Nietzsche’s ideas and transhumanism, I wondered if others had too. And it turns out, they have.

In “Nietzsche, the Overhuman, and Transhumanism”, Stefan Lorenz Sorgner argues that Nietzsche’s philosophy and the transhumanist movement share important similarities and that understanding these similarities can help us chart the future of humanity. However, Nick Bostrom, a prominent philosopher in the field of transhumanism and the author of “Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies”, has objected to this thesis.

Bostrom’s objection to Sorgner’s thesis is that Nietzsche’s philosophy is not really about transhumanism at all. According to Bostrom, Nietzsche’s focus is not on the use of technology to enhance human capabilities, but rather on the individual’s struggle for self-overcoming and the creation of new values. Bostrom argues that Nietzsche’s concept of the ubermensch is not a vision of a new kind of human being created through technology, but rather a call for individuals to transcend their current limitations and create their own values.

While Bostrom’s objection is not without merit, I believe that it ultimately misses the mark. Sorgner is not arguing that Nietzsche’s philosophy is solely about transhumanism, but rather that there are important similarities between Nietzsche’s vision of the ubermensch and the transhumanist vision of a post-human future. Both seek to transcend traditional human limitations and create a new kind of being that is more powerful, intelligent, and capable than ever before. While Nietzsche’s focus may have been more on the individual struggle for self-overcoming, the similarities between his philosophy and transhumanism are undeniable.

Furthermore, Bostrom’s objection is based on a narrow interpretation of what transhumanism entails. While it is true that transhumanism is often associated with the use of technology to enhance human capabilities, it is also concerned with the creation of new values and the pursuit of individual self-realization. Transhumanists believe that the use of technology can help us overcome the limitations of our biology and create a new kind of being that is more capable of achieving our deepest desires and goals.

Sorgner’s argument that Nietzsche’s philosophy can help us chart the future of humanity is therefore not only valid but also crucial. Nietzsche’s focus on the individual struggle for self-overcoming and the creation of new values is highly relevant to the transhumanist movement, which seeks to use technology to enhance human capabilities and create a new kind of being that is more capable of achieving our deepest desires and goals. By understanding the similarities between Nietzsche’s philosophy and the transhumanist vision of a post-human future, we can better understand the challenges and opportunities that lie ahead. We can also understand the implicit motivations behind a transhumanist philosophy.

Jürgen Habermas, the German philosopher and social theorist, is also not a fan of transhumanism. He’s got some serious concerns about the dangers of using technology to enhance human capabilities. In his view, this could lead to the creation of a new kind of inequality and threaten the very core values of human society.

In the paper, Sorgner writes: “In contrast to Bostrom, I think that significant similarities between the posthuman and the overhuman can be found on a fundamental level. Habermas agrees with me in that respect, as he has already referred to the similarities in these two ways of thinking. However, he seems to regard both of them as absurd. At least, he refers to transhumanists as a bunch of mad intellectuals who luckily have not managed to establish support for their elitist views from a bigger group of supporters.”

Habermas argues that the transhumanist movement is just part of a larger trend towards the commodification of human life. People are increasingly measured by their ability to contribute to economic growth and technological progress. This, in turn, erodes the traditional values of human dignity and social justice. Habermas believes that technological progress should be guided by ethical and democratic principles, not just by the desire for bigger, better, faster stuff.

The philosopher is also critical of the transhumanist vision of a post-human future. He sees it as a kind of techno-utopianism that completely ignores the complexity and unpredictability of human society. Creating a new kind of being that is more intelligent, powerful, and capable than humans could have unintended consequences, such as the loss of social cohesion and the emergence of new forms of inequality. A loss of social cohesion could come about by the disruption of traditional family structures while inequality could arise from further automation.

All in all, Habermas is pretty skeptical of the transhumanist movement and its vision of the future. He thinks that we should be very careful about how we use technology to enhance human capabilities. We need to take ethical and democratic principles into account and be aware of the potential risks and unintended consequences that could arise.

Inequality is the chief concern of transhumanism skeptics, who believe that this whole business of enhancing human capabilities with technology could lead to the creation of a new kind of haves and have-nots. The ones with the access to the best tech will become more powerful, more intelligent, and more capable than those without. And that’s not even mentioning the possibility of creating a new kind of being altogether! The naysayers are saying that this will upset the balance of human society and lead to new forms of inequality. But the transhumanists, well, they’re singing a different tune. They’re saying that the technology will be available to all and that it will create a level playing field. Who’s right? Only time will tell.

"A gilded No is more satisfactory than a dry yes" - Gracian